fbpx

Anxious Trade

You know a book is timely when the fund manager of Peter Thiel’s fortune is making statements like the following: “We may need a hybrid model in the future which is paradoxically more capitalistic than our capitalism today and perhaps even more socialistic than our communism of yesteryear.”

When the technologists are open to sponsoring socialism, capitalism has a problem, and it runs deep. Are Markets Moral? collects 10 academic essays that are oriented by the observation of its editors, Arthur M. Melzer and the late Steven J. Kautz: that “there is something very attractive about capitalism and something morally suspicious about it.” At the moment that America’s astonishing wealth is coming under severe scrutiny, this book suggests capitalists will struggle to offer a united front.

The contributions reveal fissures in what capitalists think their ideals are, and how they go about defending them. The book also makes clear that capitalism cannot rely on conservatives as solid allies. For example, the well-known economic historian, Deirdre McCloskey, expresses astonishment that anyone is still worried about capitalism after all the good it has done: bringing billions out of poverty. Yet some, like the late conservative Peter Augustine Lawler, are nonetheless anxious: he argues that capitalism is eroding the universities. Perhaps even more surprising, even the usually reliable Adam Smith has gone wobbly: this volume is a witness to the intense Smith scholarship over the last few decades which has left many unsure that he was a cheerleader for capitalism.

McCloskey uses India as a test case, noting that even into the 1990’s commentators insisted India’s culture could not absorb the lessons of capitalism. Of course, India’s economy transformed in the last three decades. Amidst the data points attesting to that fact is McCloskey’s important claim that over the last few decades little in the “deep culture” of India changed, but the way people talked about one another did alter significantly. Innovation and development happen, argues McCloskey, where there is a rhetoric honoring bourgeois values:

What changed in Europe, and then the world, was not the material conditions of society, or “commercialization,” or a new security of property, but the rhetoric of trade and production and improvement – that is, the way influential people talked about earning a living… and then almost everyone commenced talking this way . . . .

There is value in this thesis, but the overall effect of her argument is weakened by overreach, a tendency to extreme conflation. A case in point: “The bourgeois talk was challenged mainly by appeal to traditional values, aristocratic or religious, developing into theorized nationalism, racism, socialism, eugenics, and environmentalism.”

It is far more likely that not religion and aristocracy but mass political movements spawned by the rhetoric of equalitarianism—to which McCloskey herself is given—is responsible for the theorization of racism, socialism, eugenics, etc. If, and the claim needs examining, capitalism expresses the desire for acquisition without any larger guiding purpose, as Melzer contends in his opening comments, then there is no reason why eugenics, racism, and even variants of socialism, are excluded from capitalism.

Melzer and McCloskey—the book’s two great defenders of capitalism—are at one in their dislike of hierarchy or natural order, but, as Adam Smith argues at length, it is deference and obedience to values acknowledged as controlling and above our material passions that root conscience and give us a vantage point to be critical of our partiality and blind spots. This is what Smith calls the impartial spectator, which he describes as a demi-god. Gurcharan Das, philosopher and formerly managing director of Proctor & Gamble, is alert to this point, arguing that market exchanges surf a reservoir of trust and coherence, which, in the case of India, is secured by the ethos of dharma. He thus argues against McCloskey that something in the “deep culture” of India facilitated its commercial ignition. Das also invokes Smith, contending that Smith believed economic motivation is “highly complex and embedded in broader social habits and mores.” I think he is right about this.

Fonna Forman puts starkly a definite theme of the work: “Adam Smith might be the most widely misunderstood and abused figure in all of modern thought.” A prominent part of the book is a debate about Adam Smith’s philosophy, with Forman claiming that Smith believed public institutions important to shaping the economy. She also cheekily reminds the scorched earth capitalist types of this inconvenient fact:

It is a delicious irony of history, and an uncomfortable biographical fact for many, that Smith ended the last twelve years of his career, as his father had, working as a customs commissioner, a proud tax collector in the Scottish customs house, the very agent of British mercantilism.

Forman’s essay is full of interesting examples of public infrastructure projects transforming economies but it is a bit light on evidence that Smith believed that public investment projects are essential to flourishing commerce.

Nonetheless, Forman’s broader point about the importance of public goods to a healthy economy is a theme of two of the other essays. Channeling Pope Benedict’s analysis of distributive justice, Robert P. George argues, “business, in important ways, depends for its flourishing on things that business itself cannot produce. In many cases, these things are produced, if they are produced at all, by other social institutions. So business has a stake in the health, the flourishing of these institutions.” An example is the university. Among many fine observations, Lawler usefully identifies something he calls libertarian securitarianism: “So many libertarian Americans focus their time and treasure on perfecting personal security.” The consequence for the university is the same as for society as a whole: “They are often “libertarian” on all matters of personal morality, and even the free market, but puritanically moralistic and highly regulatory on the health-and-safety front.”

Higher education is basic to a complex economy but obsessing over material well-being means education degenerates into “techno-competency,” a reduction of the mind to technical labour in the mistaken belief that it is only from production that we can expect security. As evidence, Lawler points to cuts in the liberal arts at liberal arts colleges and filler offered through narrowly professional courses. Lawler observes that “more than ever, America is defined by a meritocracy based on productivity.”

The volume thus divides into the boosters of capitalism and those who think commerce cannot actually function without a broader social and moral coherence rooted in institutions that are prior to, and the fulcrum for, market exchanges. In Aristotelian terms, you cannot have commutative justice (contracts served) without distributive justice (social trust).

The problem for the boosters of capitalism is that its defenders seem unsure if its energy comes from desire or speech. McCloskey thinks it primarily a matter of rhetoric but Melzer thinks it more a matter of unrestrained appetite. In the opening essay, Melzer argues that capitalism is defined by two things: acquisitive lust and the moral principle of private property, i.e. “a view of justice that bases the rightful ownership of goods on production as distinguished from need.” This second element is well-taken, but the first needs work.

Melzer adds colour to the first axiom of capitalism, thusly:

It is the open-ended desire for material gain, the embrace of acquisitiveness more or less for its own sake, neither grounded in nor limited by some clear final end or purpose beyond it. Thus, in particular, it is not the love of wealth – of the use and enjoyment of money – but of endlessly increasing one’s wealth.

The problem here is that Melzer cites Hume and Smith in support. I know of no thinker of the Scottish Enlightenment who would support this proposition, and certainly Hume and Smith would be astonished by the claim. This only vaguely-hidden vitalism—“It is rather a dynamic view of life: a delight in endless forward movement for its own sake”—dates the axiom to Victorian biologism rather than the civilizational project of the eighteenth century.

Reader Discussion

Law & Liberty welcomes civil and lively discussion of its articles. Abusive comments will not be tolerated. We reserve the right to delete comments - or ban users - without notification or explanation.

on April 09, 2019 at 08:09:28 am

[…] Anxious Trade […]

read full comment
Image of Varied opinions about Adam Smith - Veneration & Refinement: The Ethics of Fashion
Varied opinions about Adam Smith - Veneration & Refinement: The Ethics of Fashion
on April 09, 2019 at 11:49:30 am

What a wonderful essay. I can see how some form of morality is necessary for markets to flourish, but at the same time, I can also see how moral codes might stifle certain types of exchanges. In any case, I would like to zero in on the great Adam Smith, since he is such a pivotal and fascinating figure whenever we talk about markets and morality. In particular, would it be correct to categorize his "Lectures on Jurisprudence" and his "The Wealth of Nations" as descriptive projects and "The Theory of Moral Sentiments" as a normative project? If so, this is-ought tension could help explain why Smith's ideas are so often misconstrued or misunderstood.

read full comment
Image of F. E. Guerra-Pujol
F. E. Guerra-Pujol
on April 09, 2019 at 12:14:20 pm

The Theory of Moral Sentiments, while it has some moral exhortations, is primarily written in terms of an explanation of actual behavior - a positive project in social sciences,

read full comment
Image of D. Allen Dalton
D. Allen Dalton
on April 09, 2019 at 15:58:31 pm

It is regretful that capitalism is on the ropes after being under assault for a century. Winston Churchill struggled with how to help the poor in the face of a society thrilled with the ideas of communism. As he worked to develop some hybrid system that transfers wealth from some above an arbitrary line to those below that arbitrary line it created a society that feels entitled to the money others have.
Analysis continues to look at symptoms as if they are cause and effect. Religious leaders, politicians and even those who feel guilty about getting wealthy pontificate on how much the wealthy 'need.' They wonder if it is moral to be successful. From their positions of wealth and power they act as if they always had those riches and always will.
Any parent who desires to purchase a vehicle for their child wonders what sort of vehicle they should get. If the individual works for it they might be more inclined to value it. If it is nicer they might be more inclined to value it.
But give them too nice a vehicle for which they have no 'skin in the game' and the individual statistically will not consider it anything more than what they deserve.
Capitalism is a series of voluntary transfers. One party values the receipt and the other party considers the sacrifice worth the value paid. Everyone goes away happy.
What can be 'moral' about a force mandating that one party must act in a certain manner towards another? Who benefits when one party feels entitled to the gains of another? What society can survive when an overwhelming majority have less than the few and feel they must take from those by force? Indeed, everyone loses as we have seen in every communist and socialist experiment across the globe.
The comparisons inevitability go to the Sweden/ Denmark political experiment as they are pseudo democratic socialists. Indeed they have a huge safety net paid for by large tax burdens but they remain essentially capitalist in their society. They also charge for certain services above and beyond what the society deems necessary. In other words, not everything is free.
Finally we look at the corrupt University system. There are no market forces to deal with in these institutions. They work to codify their services as requirements for employment and then they are immune to market forces. The costs far outstrip there worth to society or the value received by their graduates. Once again their model is not capitalist but crony-capitalism in which they make friends with the politicians and get laws in place that benefit just them.
With a century of capitalism being destroyed in the US one wonders if it can ever be corrected or if those who pontificate even know what real capitalism is/ was.

read full comment
Image of Arthur
Arthur
on April 09, 2019 at 18:19:37 pm

It is regretful that capitalism is on the ropes after being under assault for a century....

The comparisons inevitability go to the Sweden/ Denmark political experiment as they are pseudo democratic socialists. Indeed they have a huge safety net paid for by large tax burdens but they remain essentially capitalist in their society. They also charge for certain services above and beyond what the society deems necessary. In other words, not everything is free.

Could it be that the principle objective of the "assault" on capitalism is to achieve the essentially capitalistic economies of Sweden/Denmark?

I'm curious: Do the Swedes and Danes disparage the institution of capitalism as they experience it?

read full comment
Image of nobody.really
nobody.really
on April 09, 2019 at 18:27:29 pm

HI there.... The Theory of Moral Sentiments is also ab out :"is". It is a descriptive theory of moral sentiment, not a normative one. He is describing HOW moral norms work, not offering his own ethics.
I would say that Smith is mostly about "what is" in 18th century life, with the Wealth of Nations moving into the realm of speculative political economy...

It was an honor to be a part of this excellent collection!

Fonna Forman

read full comment
Image of Fonna Forman
Fonna Forman
on April 09, 2019 at 19:15:56 pm

BTW:

their tax structure is not too dissimilar from our own and some argue it is as regressive as some pundits allege ours to be.

I wonder how they do their "distributions."

read full comment
Image of gabe
gabe
on April 10, 2019 at 16:18:15 pm

My response is only anecdotal and from family members. Sweden has a social network of which they are very proud but they quietly grumbled about the taxation scheme. At one time Bjorn Borg left the country because his taxes were in excess of 100%. Eventually taxes were reduced to 25% and the economy took off like a rocket. With the influx of refugees from the Middle East the social network has been 'taxed' to a high stress level. Many are concerned that their social net is no longer adequate and they can't afford to pay more for it.

We suffer from a feeling that the government must cure all ills. With the passage of 16th Amendment the government has a license to take as much money as it wants. Crony Capitalism took off at a rate far beyond what had taken place during the 1800's. Today every politician buys votes with voters money and when you add in Keynes there is no limit to the level of debt.

What is the proper level of taxation? Many settle on 25% based on what we are paying now. (6.2% SS +1.45% Med+12% avg FITW) The average citizen pays roughly 20% and their employer adds in another 8%. However, the level of taxation can never keep up with the demand for spending.

read full comment
Image of Arthur
Arthur

Law & Liberty welcomes civil and lively discussion of its articles. Abusive comments will not be tolerated. We reserve the right to delete comments - or ban users - without notification or explanation.

Related