fbpx

The Empty Bromide of Religious Neutrality

The history of American public education may be told as a history of gradual secularization driven not by religious neutrality but religious enthusiasm.

In the American colonies and well into the nineteenth century, the churches took primary charge of education. Even where public schools were established, their curriculum was distinctively Christian. Early nineteenth century Massachusetts schools were at first colored by a kind of pietistic Calvinism, after which there was an effort to diminish their distinctive Congregationalism. Horace Mann, that emblem of the early development of the government school, himself supported “religious instruction in our schools to the extremest verge to which it can be carried without invading those rights of conscience which are established by the laws of God and guaranteed by the Constitution of the State [of Massachusetts].”[1]

Church education was thus fitfully replaced by varieties of government sponsored and administered Christian education. As time passed, the quality of the religious instruction became progressively diluted—less religiously specific, certainly, but not less specifically religious. Justice Frankfurter once praised the public school as “a symbol of our secular unity,”[2] but he might have more precisely described it as a symbol of our religious division. The increasing secularity of public education grew not so much from the struggle between rival advocates of secular and religious education as from disagreement about the properly religious character of the government school—about the sort of religion needed to sustain the republic.

In the contemporary period, as the liberal Protestantism of the public school has been drained of any vestigial Protestantism, there remains only the liberalism as the embodiment of the nation’s civic ideals. Like all government organs, public schools are now bound by the Supreme Court’s constitutional injunction not to “endorse” religion in ways that make non-adherents feel like political outsiders (at least, so the political insiders have it). The secular projects and aspirations of the liberal state sustain the American polity.

There is a parallel history concerning the American state’s posture toward religious schools, the chief case of which is the Catholic parochial school. Catholics were driven by the government-endorsed Protestantism of the nineteenth century to adopt a separate system of privately funded schooling that by the mid-twentieth century educated millions of students. Those that opposed this divergence believed—not without reason—that a uniform, government-endorsed Protestantism was an important force of American civic acculturation for the young.

They conceived a name for the separate Catholic system—“sectarian” education—and found champions in Ulysses S. Grant and James G. Blaine, Senator from Maine, Speaker of the House of Representatives, and a Republican candidate for president in the election of 1884, who pressed for a federal constitutional amendment explicitly forbidding any financial aid to “sectarian” institutions. This was done precisely in the name of the radical “separation of church and state”—not because amendment advocates like Grant and Blaine believed that the Constitution required separationism, but because they thought it didn’t. Though the federal amendment failed (passing in the House but falling in the Senate only two votes shy of the 2/3 required for constitutional amendment), proscriptions against the funding of “sectarian” schools found their way into many state constitutions in later years in so-called “Blaine Amendments.”

This failure of the federal constitutional amendment, in part, led those desiring a strong version of separationism to focus now on constitutional interpretation and invented genealogies concerning the Establishment Clause’s true or essential separationist principle. In time, this approach met with far greater success. Beginning in the late 1940s and until fairly recently, church-state separationism represented the Supreme Court’s favored approach to Establishment Clause issues involving government funding of religious institutions. Most recently, the Court has instead preferred a seemingly more egalitarian regime of “neutrality”—sameness of treatment for religion and non-religion. Direct and preferential aid to religious schools is not neutral. But indirect aid may be. Thus the Supreme Court has held that a municipality’s school voucher program, in which participants could spend government funds to send their children to parochial schools, reflected a neutral fiscal allocation—one that treated religion and non-religion equally and so neutrally under a system of “truly private choice.”[3]

A recent decision by the Colorado Supreme Court, however, illustrates how decidedly partial an ostensibly neutral legal regime actually can be. Colorado’s Douglas County School District had instituted a program through which certain students accepted by private schools—religious and nonreligious—were eligible to receive a tuition scholarship. The money went to the students’ families, who would then pay it to the school they had chosen to attend. Roughly 93% of participating students chose to attend a religious school.

The key issue in the case was this program’s constitutionality under Colorado’s 1876 Blaine Amendment, enacted at the zenith of the controversy concerning the civic and religious character of public education and the government’s hostility toward Catholic education. Colorado’s version provides that no organ of the state

shall ever make any appropriation, or pay from any public fund or moneys whatever, anything in aid of any church or sectarian society, or for any sectarian purpose, or to help support or sustain any school, academy, seminary, college, university or other literary or scientific institution, controlled by any church or sectarian denomination whatsoever.

The court interpreted this language as broadly as it possibly could to forbid any aid—direct or indirect—to “sectarian” institutions. It refused to consider the extensive history of the word “sectarian” in this context, instead referring to Black’s Law Dictionary to reach the willfully historically obtuse conclusion that “sectarian” is synonymous with “religious.” Yet not even its own preferred source supports that equivalence: Black’s Law Dictionary defines “sectarian” as “[o]f, relating to, or involving a particular religious sect; esp., supporting a particular religious group and its beliefs.” No matter: the text of the Amendment, said the court, unequivocally prohibits the use of any moneys that might even indirectly “support” or “sustain” religious schools by making it easier for students to attend. That interpretation, as the dissent points out, would invalidate state programs for the maintenance of basic infrastructure and safety measures applicable to all schools. Along the way, the court makes a hash of its prior decisions, purporting to distinguish another case in which it upheld a state grant to private religious undergraduate educational institutions so long as they were not “pervasively sectarian.” The exclusion of “pervasively sectarian” schools in a government-funding program passes Blaine Amendment muster, it seems, while the inclusion of “sectarian” schools does not.

Focusing on these details of Colorado law, however, obscures certain larger questions. If “sectarian” truly does mean “Catholic,” and even if it means, as Black’s Law Dictionary says, “of, relating to, or involving a particular religious sect,” then any state Blaine Amendment with this language would be subject to constitutional challenge under the Supreme Court’s free exercise law. “Sectarian” does not sound particularly neutral; or, to the extent it does, it sounds in the rather counterintuitive neutrality of state-endorsed religious hostility. Yet even this perspective on the question of neutrality passes over the colossal non-neutrality of the government’s systematic and exclusive funding of its own putatively religion-neutral schools, to the detriment of able students—many of them from poor and educationally underserved communities—who would greatly benefit from private religious schooling. Neutrality between religion and non-religion seems to demand a plainly partial allocation of resources. Or, one variety of government neutrality—no funding of religious schools—obstructs the achievement of another—educational opportunity.

The question of the place of religion in American educational life—whether in the nation’s public schools or in its position on private religious schools—will not be answered by neutrality talk, for the fundamental reason that nothing in the projects of American education is or ever has been neutral toward religion. From the very first, it was precisely the non-neutrality of the state toward religion that has been one of the prime catalysts of cultural and legal development in American education policy, public and private. There is an understandable tendency among some opponents of state Blaine Amendments such as Colorado’s to reduce them to simple expressions of non-neutral anti-Catholicism. Often they were that, but they were more.

To understand them merely in these terms—as lamentable examples of “discrimination”—domesticates them. It consigns them to a history from which we have happily progressed now that we have entered an epoch in which the making of discriminations of any kind is taboo. It puffs us up with the Whiggish certitude that to repudiate the Blaine Amendments is to rid ourselves decisively of the very real problem they addressed. That problem—how to foster through education the common civic culture upon which the American polity, even still, depends—does not vanish by easy, self-congratulatory resort to the voguish platitudes of antidiscrimination. The Blaine Amendments were woefully inadequate responses to that problem, but responses nonetheless. The empty bromide of religious neutrality is no response at all.

[1] As quoted in Leo Pfeffer, Church, State and Freedom 332 (1967).

[2] McCollum v. Board of Education, 333 U.S. 203, 217 (1948) (Frankfurter, J., concurring).

[3] Zelman v. Simmons-Harris, 536 U.S. 639 (2002).

Reader Discussion

Law & Liberty welcomes civil and lively discussion of its articles. Abusive comments will not be tolerated. We reserve the right to delete comments - or ban users - without notification or explanation.

on July 24, 2015 at 11:44:15 am

The question of the place of religion in American educational life—whether in the nation’s public schools or in its position on private religious schools—will not be answered by neutrality talk, for the fundamental reason that nothing in the projects of American education is or ever has been neutral toward religion.

Perhaps this reflects a semantic problem, but I suspect it reflects a conceptual problem born of a semantic shortcut. Specifically, when the law speaks of neutrality, equality, or discrimination, presumably it speaks of these things relative to some relevant standard such as “bona fide governmental interest” – but that qualifying phrase often goes unstated.

Thus, pretty much every school is unequal to every other with respect to street address -- but government has no interest in this type of inequality. Employers regularly discriminate among applicants on the basis of talent and experience -- but government has no interest in discouraging this type of discrimination. We don’t really believe in equality and non-discrimination except as they are related to some relevant standard.

I want schools to be neutral except insofar as necessary to achieve the bona fide governmental purposes of education. What are those? Arguably the state has a bona fide interest in disseminating certain skills widely and, more controversially, teaching some modicum of values necessary to permit society to endure (“social cohesion”).

But would it be possible to create a school that promoted these purposes yet was “neutral” in every variable regarding religion/world view? No. The choice to permit teachers to hug students or not conveys a world view about the human body, and about appropriate relationships between children and unrelated adults. The choice to acknowledge birthdays conveys a world view about individualism. The choice to control what kids wear and how they act, to hold school dances or not, to have competitive teams and to honor their competitive achievements, to promote people with [insert a suspect category here] into positions of authority, etc. – ALL convey values.

Because running a school inevitably involves conveying values, ideally the state that eschewed the Establishment of Religion would stay out of that business except as a provider of last resort. (Or nearly last. If we’re going to compel kids to attend school, we don’t want to turn government into a tool for promoting the religious views of the sole provider of educational services. Compulsory attendance at a private school would pose many of the same problems as compulsory incarceration in a private prison.) Rather, the state should contract for the relevant services (e.g., via vouchers), and test to ensure that it is receiving what it has paid for.

More generally, it would be nice if government could stop discriminating on the basis of religion entirely. Again, that would not mean a religious quota system; it would mean acting solely to promote bona fide governmental interests without regard to religious affiliation. Both the military and state-run universities should accept the best applicants that apply. True, if we discover that a disproportionate share of people accepted into the military are Southern Baptists, or people accepted into the university are Jews, that might provide a basis to investigate whether bias had crept into the process. But assuming government has sufficiently objective, relevant standards for its decisions, then these disparities would be irrelevant – that is, unless someone could make the argument that it *is* relevant, specifically, to a bona fide governmental purpose. (E.g., Is there cause to believe that Southern Baptists are organizing a military coup?)

In short, I embrace a concept of neutrality -- but it merely refers to the duty of governmental agents to act to promote bona fide purposes and not to exercise their discretion in a manner unrelated to those purposes. To the extent the Blaine Amendments support this, I support them; to the extent the Blaine Amendments compel government to discriminate on the basis of religious affiliation, I oppose them.

read full comment
Image of nobody.really
nobody.really
on July 24, 2015 at 21:42:16 pm

[…] More. […]

read full comment
Image of Bromide
Bromide
on July 25, 2015 at 12:04:17 pm

"Because running a school inevitably involves conveying values, ideally the state that eschewed the Establishment of Religion would stay out of that business except as a provider of last resort"

Absotively! Are you ready to launch a campaign to assure "equality" of political perspective in the schools.
I still have money in the piggybank to fund it?

Your points are very well taken. I wonder, however, how many citizens are open to even considering such a view.
Yes, we may blame teachers unions (see Abood posts among other issues mentioned), leftists, etc - BUT, really it is of our own doing. We allow this to happen. Just as in the late 19th century anti-Catholic bias prepared the soil for the Blaine amendments, whilst the populace sat idly by (or cheered them on), our unwillingness to confront the ideologues on local / state school boards allow for the current sorry state of education in both our traditions and history, both of which are the distorted end-products of a particular ideological slant.

(Of course, if you don't act quickly, I may have to reserve the monies in the piggybank for my young grandson so that he may attend a decent private school - Oh, the (in)humanity of it!

read full comment
Image of gabe
gabe

Law & Liberty welcomes civil and lively discussion of its articles. Abusive comments will not be tolerated. We reserve the right to delete comments - or ban users - without notification or explanation.

Related